Respect Life - Church Teachings

olguadalupeChurch Teachings

For detailed information on Church teachings, please refer to the United States Conference of Catholic Bishop’s website: http://www.usccb.org

The following quotations are selected from Catholic documents and statements. For copies contact your diocesan Respect Life office.

Abortion

“Human life must be respected and protected absolutely from the moment of conception. From the first moment of existence, a human being must be recognized as having the rights of a person—among which is the inviolable right of every innocent being to life.” CCC 2270

“The first right of the human person is the right to life. He has other goods of which some are more precious, but this one is fundamental – the condition of all the others. Hence it must be protected above all others. It does not belong to society nor does it belong to public authority in any form to recognize this right for some and not for others. . . It is not recognition by another that constitute this right. This right is antecedent to its recognition; it demands recognition and it is strictly unjust to refuse it.”

Declaration on Procured Abortion No.11.

“Human life must be respected and protected absolutely from the moment of conception. From the first moment of his existence, the human being must be recognized as having the rights of a person among which is the inviolable right of every innocent being to life.” cf. CDF. Donum Vitae 1.1. Catechism of the Catholic Church, 1994, #2270.

“Since the first century the Church has affirmed the moral evil of every procured abortion. This teaching has not changed and remains unchangeable. Direct abortion, that is to say, abortion willed either as an end or a means, is gravely contrary to the moral law: You shall not kill the embryo by abortion and shall not make the newborn perish.” Catechism of the Catholic Church, 1994, #2271 Didache 2:2; cf ep. Bamabus, 19:5; Epistle to Diognetus 5; TertuIliiian, Apol. 9.

“God, the Lord of life, has entrusted to men the noble mission of safeguarding life, and men must carry it out in a manner worthy of themselves. Life must be protected with the utmost care from the moment of conception: abortion and infanticide are abominable crimes.” Ibid. #2271; Gaudium et Spes, 51: 3

“The inalienable right to life of every innocent human individual is a constitutive element of civil society and of its legislation:

The inalienable rights of persons must be recognized and respected by civil society and the political authority. These human rights depend neither on single individuals nor parents; nor do they represent a concession made by society and the state: they belong to human nature and are inherent in the person by virtue of the creative act from which the person took his origin. Among such fundamental rights one should mention in this regard every human being’s right to life and physical integrity from the moment of conception until death.”CDF, instr. Donum Vitae Ill

“The moment a positive law deprives a category of human beings of the protection which civil legislation ought to accord them, the state is denying them equality of all before the law. When the state does not place its power at the service of the rights of each citizen, and in particular of the more vulnerable, the very foundations of a state based on law are undermined… As a consequence of the respect and protection which must be insured for the unborn child from the moment of conception, the law must provide appropriate penal sanctions for every deliberate violation of the child’s rights.” Catechism of the Catholic Church, 1994, #2273

Infanticide

“…We see the defense of the right to life of handicapped persons as a matter of particular urgency, however, because the presence of handicapping conditions is not infrequently used as a rationale for abortion. Moreover those severely handicapped babies who are permitted to be born are sometimes denied ordinary and usual medical procedures. All too often, abortion and postnatal neglect are promoted by arguing that the handicapped infant will survive only to suffer a life of pain and deprivation. We find this reasoning appalling. Society’s frequent indifference to the plight of handicapped citizens is a problem that cries aloud for solutions based on justice and conscience, not violence. All people have a clear duty to do what lies in their power to improve living conditions for handicapped people, rather than ignoring them or attempting to eliminate them as a burden not worth dealing with.”

Pastoral Statement of the United States Catholic Bishops on Handicapped People, nos. 8 & 9.

Euthanasia

“It is necessary to state firmly once more that nothing and no one can in any way permit the killing of an innocent human being, whether a fetus or an embryo, an infant or an adult, an old person or one suffering from an incurable disease or a person who is dying. Furthermore, no one is permitted to ask for this act of killing, either for himself or herself or for another person entrusted to his or her care, nor can he or she consent to it, either explicitly or implicitly nor can any authority legitimately recommend or permit such an action. For it is a question of the violation of the divine law, an offense against the dignity of the human person, a crime against life and an attack on humanity.” Vatican Declaration on Euthanasia, 1980.

“Whatever its motives and means, direct euthanasia consists of putting an end to the lives of handicapped, sick, or dying persons. It is morally unacceptable. Thus an act or omission which, of itself or by intention, causes death in order to terminate pain constitutes a murder gravely contrary to the dignity of the human person and to respect due to the living God, his Creator. The error of judgement into which one can fall in good faith does not change the nature of this murderous act, which must always be forbidden and excluded.” cf #2277.

“Discontinuing medical procedures that are burdensome, dangerous, extraordinary, or disproportionate to the expected outcome can be legitimate; it is the refusal of ‘over zealous’ treatment. Here one does not will to cause death; one’s inability to impede it is merely accepted. The decisions should be made by the patient if he is competent and able or, if not, by those legally entitled to act for the patient whose reasonable will and legitimate interests must always be respected.” Ibid. #2278.

“Even if death is considered imminent, the care ordinarily owed to a sick person cannot legitimately be interrupted. The use of analgesics to alleviate the suffering of the dying, even at the risk of shortening his days, can be morally in conformity to human dignity if death is not willed, as an end to a means, but only foreseen and tolerated as inevitable. Palliative care constitutes a privileged form of disinterested charity. For this reason it must be encouraged.” Ibid. #2279.

“The witnesses of the New Covenant speak of the greatness of the Redemption, accomplished through the suffering of Christ…Christ has also raised human suffering to the level of the Redemption.  Thus each man, in his suffering, can also become a sharer in the redemptive suffering of Christ.  The texts of the New Testament express this concept in many places.  In the Second Letter to the Corinthians, the Apostle writes: ‘We are afflicted in every way, but not crushed; perplexed, but not driven to despair; persecuted, but not forsaken; struck down, but not destroyed; always carrying in the body the death of Jesus, so that the life of Jesus may also be manifested in our bodies.  For while we live we are always being given up to death for Jesus’ sake, so that the life of Jesus may be manifested in our mortal flesh…knowing that He who raised the Lord Jesus will raise us also with Jesus’.”

                                     –Pope John Paul II, On the Meaning of Human Suffering

Aging

“To turn our attention to the aging is to realize how much they are a part of God’s plan for the world, with their mission to fulfill their unique contribution to make, their problems to solve, their burdens to bear. The Catholic Church willingly lends her support to efforts that encourage the elderly themselves to look with realism and serenity on the role that God has assigned to them. With the wisdom and experience of their lives they have entered a period of extraordinary grace with new opportunities for prayer and union with God.”

Active Aging, Texts of Pope John Paul II

Persons with Disabilities

“It is not enough merely to affirm the rights of people with disabilities. We must actively work to make them real in the fabric of modern society. Recognizing that individuals with disabilities have a claim to our respect because they are persons, they share in the one redemption of Christ, and because they contribute to our society by their activity within it, the Church must become an advocate for and with them… Individuals and organizations at every level within the Church should minister to persons with disabilities by serving their personal and social needs…In touching the lives of men, women, and children with disabilities we come closest to imitating Jesus’ own example, which should be always before our eyes.” Pastoral Statement of the United States Catholic Bishops, on People with Disabilities, no.11.

Natural Family Planning“Called to give life, spouses share in the creative power and fatherhood of God. Married couples should regard it as their proper mission to transmit human life and to educate their children; they should realize that they are thereby cooperating with the love of God the Creator and are, in a certain sense, its interpreters. They will fulfill this duty with a sense of human and Christian responsibility.” Gaudium et Spes 50-2 Catechism of the Catholic Church, 1994 #2367

“A particular aspect of this responsibility concerns the regulation of births. For just reasons, spouses may wish to space the births of Their children. It is their duty to make certain that their desire is not motivated by selfishness but is in conformity with the generosity appropriate to responsible parenthood. Moreover, they should conform their behavior to the objective criteria of morality. When it is a question of harmonizing married love with the responsible transmission of life, the morality of the behavior does not depend on sincere intention and evaluation of motives alone; but it must be determined by objective criteria, criteria drawn from the nature of the person and his acts, criteria that respect the total meaning of mutual self-giving and human procreation in the context of true love; this is possible only if the virtue of married chastity is practiced with sincerity of heart.” G.S. 51-3; Ibid. #2368

“Periodic continence, that is, the methods of birth regulation based on self-observation and the use of infertile periods, is in conformity with the objective criteria of morality. These methods respect the bodies of the spouses, encourage tenderness between them, and favor the education of an authentic freedom. In contrast, every action which, whether in anticipation of the conjugal act, or in its accomplishment, or in the development of its natural consequences, purposes, whether as an end or as a means, to render procreation impossible is intrinsically evil.”

Humanae Vitae 14; Ibid. #2370

“Thus the innate language that expresses the total reciprocal self-giving of husband and wife is overlaid, through contraception, by an objectively contradictory language, namely, that of not giving oneself totally to the other. This leads not only to a positive refusal to be open to life but also to a falsification of the inner truth of conjugal love, which is called upon to give itself in personal totality… The difference, both anthropological and cycle…involves in the final analysis two irreconcilable concepts of the human person and of human sexuality.”

Pope John Paul II, Apostolic Exhortation, 1981; Familiaris Consorto 32; Ibid. #2370


Stem Cell Research

What Every Catholic Should Know About Stem Cell Research

What Are Stem Cells and Why the Interest in Them?Stem cells are cells that have the potential to become many other kinds of cells, depending on the signals they receive. They theoretically provide avenues for replacing damaged or non-functioning tissue to treat many kinds of diseases. Stem cells are found from the beginning of embryonic development throughout adult life.

Is the Church Opposed to All Stem Cell Research? NO! The church is not opposed to the use of stem cells obtained from adults because obtaining them does not harm the person. Adult stem cells have been successfully obtained from umbilical cord blood, skin, bone marrow and even fat! Adult stem cells and other ethically acceptable alternatives have already helped hundreds of thousands of patients and new clinical uses expand almost weekly. For example, adult stem cells have helped patients with juvenile diabetes, spinal cord injury, immune deficiency, and visual impairment.

The Church is opposed to the use of stem cells obtained from human embryos because the embryo is killed in the process of obtaining his/her stem cells. To date, embryonic stem cells have not helped a single human patient or demonstrated any therapeutic benefit.

What is an Embryo and Where do Scientists get Embryos for Research?  “Human development is a continuous process that begins when an [egg] from a female is fertilized by a sperm…from a male.” The resulting cell, a zygote or embryo is the beginning of a new human being” and “marked the beginning of each of us as a unique individual.” (Moore and Persaud The Developing Human: Clinically Oriented Embryology 6th Edition, 1998 pg 2 and 18). Thus, as a member of our human family, the embryo, like the fetus, infant, adolescent and adult is a sacred and inviolable human person made in the image and likeness of God and may not be used for the benefit of someone or something else.

The embryos killed for their stem cells are about one week old and have grown to about 200 cells. Most of the embryos obtained for research come from in vitro fertilization (infertility) clinics. In these clinics, embryos are produced in petri dishes, then implanted in the wombs of women who are experiencing difficulty conceiving a pregnancy. Typically, more embryos are produced than are initially implanted in the mother in case future attempts at pregnancy are sought. If additional pregnancies are not sought, the parents must eventually choose to unthaw and destroy the embryos, give them to another couple who seeks a pregnancy, or donate them to science where they will be destroyed as part of research.

The Catholic Church teaches that in vitro fertilization and other reproductive technologies that replace or substitute for the conjugal act are contrary to God’s design for procreation and therefore immoral. Reproductive technologies that assist the conjugal act to produce a child (such as fertility drugs or natural procreative technologies) respect God’s design and are morally acceptable.

If the Embryos will be Destroyed Anyway, Why Not Use Them for Research?  In answering this question, one must remember the biological fact that embryos are human beings and therefore possess the same sacred dignity as any other human being. We, therefore, must not do to embryos what we would not do to more developed human beings (e.g. infants, adolescents, adults). There are probably hundreds of thousands of people who are currently terminally ill and will die soon. The likelihood that these human beings will die soon anyway would not legitimize killing them for medical research, even if it could help cure other people. Similarly, the likelihood that embryonic human beings may die soon does not make it acceptable to kill them for the benefits of others.

What Does President Bush’s Stem Cell Decision Mean? On August 9, President Bush announced that he will allow limited federal funding of embryonic stem cell research. No funding will be allowed for research that involves future destruction of human embryos. That’s good. The president deserves credit for prohibiting at least for now, the use of taxpayer dollars for research that directly destroys human embryos. But the President will allow funding of research on more than 60 existing stem cell lines [a cell line is basically a culture of cells that continues to grow on its own] that were created from human embryos destroyed specifically for the purpose of creating these stem cell lines. That’s bad. The President’s rationale is that since these embryos have already been destroyed and the cell lines do not require any further killing, it is morally permissible to fund research on these cell lines.

There are several reasons why funding these existing stem cell lines is bad. First, it is quite likely that even limited government funding of this research might encourage more killing of embryos for more such research by privately funded companies by (a) removing some of its ethical stigma and (b) providing the “seed money” for the early non profitable stages of the research. Second, scientists will undoubtedly continue to kill additional embryos (and create new cell lines) with private funds and if these 60 existing lines prove inadequate they will recommend these new cell lines for use in federally funded research. Under the president’s current rationale, it will be difficult for him to reject these new cell lines since the embryos used to create the cell line “have already been destroyed.” Finally, it is possible that the research on these existing stem cell lines could result in therapies or cures that rely upon the destruction of more embryos.

All of these likely results are scandalous. Even though current taxpayer dollarswill not fund research that kills human embryos, any taxpayer funding of embryonic stem cell research will likely result in the killing of more human embryos. It will also spread an already pervasive view that it is permissible to kill some human beings for the benefit of other human beings.

For further information on stem cell research, check out these websites: http://www.usccb.org/prolife/issues/bioethic/stemcell/index.shtml– Bioethics and Reproductive Technologies

or

http://www.stemcellresearch.org.


Questions about Medically Assisted

Nutrition and Hydration

In what follows we apply these well-established moral principles to the difficult issue of providing medically assisted nutrition and hydration to persons who are seriously ill, disabled or persistently unconscious. We recognize the complexity involved in applying these principles to individual cases and acknowledge that, at this time and on this particular issue, our applications do not have the same authority as the principles themselves.

1. Is the withholding or withdrawing of medically assisted nutrition and hydration always a direct killing?

In answering this question one should avoid two extremes.

First, it is wrong to say that this could not be a matter of killing simply because it involves an omission rather than a positive action. In fact a deliberate omission may be an effective and certain way to kill, especially to kill someone weakened by illness. Catholic teaching condemns as euthanasia “an action or an omission which of itself or by intention causes death, in order that all suffering may in this way be eliminated.” Thus “euthanasia includes not only active mercy killing but also the omission of treatment when the purpose of the omission is to kill the patient.”[11]

Second, we should not assume that all or most decisions to withhold or withdraw medically assisted nutrition and hydration are attempts to cause death. To be sure, any patient will die if all nutrition and hydration are withheld.[12] But sometimes other causes are at work — for example, the patient may be imminently dying, whether feeding takes place or not, from an already existing terminal condition. At other times, although the shortening of the patient’s life is one foreseeable result of an omission, the real purpose of the omission was to relieve the patient of a particular procedure that was of limited usefulness to the patient or unreasonably burdensome for the patient and the patient’s family or caregivers. This kind of decision should not be equated with a decision to kill or with suicide.

The harsh reality is that some who propose withdrawal of nutrition and hydration from certain patients do directly intend to bring about a patient’s death, and would even prefer a change in the law to allow for what they see as more “quick and painless” means to cause death.[13] In other words, nutrition and hydration (whether orally administered or medically assisted) are sometimes withdrawn not because a patient is dying, but precisely because a patient is not dying (or not dying quickly) and someone believes it would be better if he or she did, generally because the patient is perceived as having an unacceptably low “quality of life” or as imposing burdens on others.[14]

When deciding whether to withhold or withdraw medically assisted nutrition and hydration, or other forms of life support, we are called by our moral tradition to ask ourselves: What will my decision do for this patient? And what am I trying to achieve by doing it? We must be sure that it is not our intent to cause the patient’s death — either for its own sake or as a means to achieving some other goal such as the relief of suffering.

2. Is medically assisted nutrition and hydration a form of “treatment” or “care”?

Catholic teaching provides that a person in the final stages of dying need not accept “forms of treatment that would only secure a precarious and burdensome prolongation of life,” but should still receive “the normal care due to the sick person in similar cases.”[15] All patients deserve to receive normal care out of respect for their inherent dignity as persons. As Pope John Paul II has said, a decision to forgo “purely experimental or ineffective interventions” does not “dispense from the valid therapeutic task of sustaining life or from assistance with the normal means of sustaining life. Science, even when it is unable to heal, can and should care for and assist the sick.”[16] But the teaching of the Church has not resolved the question whether medically assisted nutrition and hydration should always be seen as a form of normal care.[17]

Almost everyone agrees that oral feeding, when it can be accepted and assimilated by a patient, is a form of care owed to all helpless people. Christians should be especially sensitive to this obligation, because giving food and drink to those in need is an important expression of Christian love and concern (Mt. 10:42 and 25:35; Mk. 9:41). But our obligations become less clear when adequate nutrition and hydration require the skills of trained medical personnel and the use of technologies that may be perceived as very burdensome — that is, as intrusive, painful or repugnant. Such factors vary from one type of feeding procedure to another, and from one patient to another, making it difficult to classify all feeding procedures as either “care” or “treatment.”

Perhaps this dilemma should be viewed in a broader context. Even medical “treatments” are morally obligatory when they are “ordinary” means–that is, if they provide a reasonable hope of benefit and do not involve excessive burdens. Therefore we believe people should make decisions in light of a simple and fundamental insight: Out of respect for the dignity of the human person, we are obliged to preserve our own lives, and help others preserve theirs, by the use of means that have a reasonable hope of sustaining life without imposing unreasonable burdens on those we seek to help, that is, on the patient and his or her family and community.

We must therefore address the question of benefits and burdens next, recognizing that a full moral analysis is only possible when one knows the effects of a given procedure on a particular patient.

3. What are the benefits of medically assisted nutrition and hydration?

According to international codes of medical ethics, a physician will see a medical procedure as appropriate “if in his or her judgment it offers hope of saving life, reestablishing health or alleviating suffering.”[18]

Nutrition and hydration, whether provided in the usual way or with medical assistance, do not by themselves remedy pathological conditions, except those caused by dietary deficiencies. But patients benefit from them in several ways. First, for all patients who can assimilate them, suitable food and fluids sustain life, and providing them normally expresses loving concern and solidarity with the helpless. Second, for patients being treated with the hope of a cure, appropriate food and fluids are an important element of sound health care. Third, even for patients who are imminently dying and incurable, food and fluids can prevent the suffering that may arise from dehydration, hunger and thirst.

The benefit of sustaining and fostering life is fundamental, because life is our first gift from a loving God and the condition for receiving His other gifts. But sometimes even food and fluids are no longer effective in providing this benefit, because a patient has entered the final stage of a terminal condition. At such times we should make the dying person as comfortable as possible and provide nursing care and proper hygiene as well as companionship and appropriate spiritual aid. Such a person may lose all desire for food and drink and even be unable to ingest them. Initiating medically assisted feeding or intravenous fluids in this case may increase the patient’s discomfort while providing no real benefit; ice chips or sips of water may instead be appropriate to provide comfort and counteract the adverse effects of dehydration.[19] Even in the case of the imminently dying patient, of course, any action or omission that of itself or by intention causes death is to be absolutely rejected.

As Christians who trust in the promise of eternal life, we recognize that death does not have the final word. Accordingly we need not always prevent death until the last possible moment; but we should never intentionally cause death or abandon the dying person as though he or she were unworthy of care and respect.

4. What are the burdens of medically assisted nutrition and hydration?  Our tradition does not demand heroic measures in fulfilling the obligation to sustain life. A person may legitimately refuse even procedures that effectively prolong life, if he or she believes they would impose excessively grave burdens on himself or herself, or on his or her family and community. Catholic theologians have traditionally viewed medical treatment as excessively burdensome if it is “too painful, too damaging to the patient’s bodily self and functioning, too psychologically repugnant to the patient, too restrictive of the patient’s liberty and preferred activities, too suppressive of the patient’s mental life, or too expensive.”[20]

Because assessment of these burdens necessarily involves some subjective judgments, a conscious and competent patient is generally the best judge of whether a particular burden or risk is too grave to be tolerated in his or her own case. But because of the serious consequences of withdrawing all nutrition and hydration, patients and those helping them make decisions should assess such burdens or risks with special care.

Here we offer some brief reflections and cautions regarding the kinds of burdens sometimes associated with medically assisted nutrition and hydration.

Physical risks and burdens

The risks and objective complications of medically assisted nutrition and hydration will depend on the procedure used and the condition of the patient. In a given case a feeding procedure may become harmful or even life-threatening. (These medical data are discussed at length in an Appendix to this paper.)

If the risks and burdens of a particular feeding procedure are deemed serious enough to warrant withdrawing it, we should not automatically deprive the patient of all nutrition and hydration but should ask whether another procedure is feasible that would be less burdensome. We say this because some helpless patients, including some in a “persistent vegetative state,” receive tube feedings not because they cannot swallow food at all but because tube feeding is less costly and difficult for health care personnel.[21]

Moreover, because burdens are assessed in relation to benefits, we should ask whether the risks and discomfort of a feeding procedure are really excessive as compared with the adverse effects of dehydration or malnutrition.

Psychological burdens on the patient

Many people see feeding tubes as frightening or even as bodily violations. Assessments of such burdens are necessarily subjective; they should not be dismissed on that account, but we offer some practical cautions to help prevent abuse.

First, in keeping with our moral teaching against the intentional causing of death by omission, one should distinguish between repugnance to a particular procedure and repugnance to life itself. The latter may occur when a patient views a life of helplessness and dependency on others as itself a heavy burden, leading him or her to wish or even to pray for death. Especially in our achievement-oriented society, the burden of living in such a condition may seem to outweigh any possible benefit of medical treatment and even lead a person to despair. But we should not assume that the burdens in such a case always outweigh the benefits; for the sufferer, given good counseling and spiritual support, may be brought again to appreciate the precious gift of life.

Second, our tradition recognizes that when treatment decisions are made, “account will have to be taken of the reasonable wishes of the patient and the patient’s family, as also of the advice of the doctors who are specially competent in the matter.”[22] The word “reasonable” is important here. Good health care providers will try to help patients assess psychological burdens with full information and without undue fear of unfamiliar procedures.[23] A well-trained and compassionate hospital chaplain can provide valuable personal and spiritual support to patients and families facing these difficult situations.

Third, we should not assume that a feeding procedure is inherently repugnant to all patients without specific evidence. In contrast to Americans’ general distaste for the idea of being supported by “tubes and machines,” some studies indicate surprisingly favorable views of medically assisted nutrition and hydration among patients and families with actual experience of such procedures.[24]

Economic and other burdens on caregivers  While some balk at the idea, in principle cost can be a valid factor in decisions about life support. For example, money spent on expensive treatment for one family member may be money otherwise needed for food, housing and other necessities for the rest of the family. Here, also, we offer some cautions.

First, particularly when a form of treatment “carries a risk or is burdensome” on other grounds, a critically ill person may have a legitimate and altruistic desire “not to impose excessive expense on the family or the community.”[25] Even for altruistic reasons a patient should not directly intend his or her own death by malnutrition or dehydration, but may accept an earlier death as a consequence of his or her refusal of an unreasonably expensive treatment. Decisions by others to deny an incompetent patient medically assisted nutrition and hydration for reasons of cost raise additional concerns about justice to the individual patient, who could wrongly be deprived of life itself to serve the less fundamental needs of others.

Second, we do not think individual decisions about medically assisted nutrition and hydration should be determined by macro-economic concerns such as national budget priorities and the high cost of health care. These social problems are serious, but it is by no means established that they require depriving chronically ill and helpless patients of effective and easily tolerated measures that they need to survive.[26]

Third, tube feeding alone is generally not very expensive and may cost no more than oral feeding.[27] What is seen by many as a grave financial and emotional burden on caregivers is the total long-term care of severely debilitated patients, who may survive for many years with no life support except medically assisted nutrition and hydration and nursing care.

The difficulties families may face in this regard, and their need for improved financial and other assistance from the rest of society, should not be underestimated. While caring for a helpless loved one can provide many intangible benefits to family members and bring them closer together, the responsibilities of care can also strain even close and loving family relationships; complex medical decisions must be made under emotionally difficult circumstances not easily appreciated by those who have never faced such situations.

Even here, however, we must try to think through carefully what we intend by withdrawing medically assisted nutrition and hydration. Are we deliberately trying to make sure that the patient dies, in order to relieve caregivers of the financial and emotional burdens that will fal

l upon them if the patient survives? Are we really implementing a decision to withdraw all other forms of care, precisely because the patient offers so little response to the efforts of caregivers? Decisions like these seem to reach beyond the weighing of burdens and benefits of medically assisted nutrition and hydration as such.

In the context of official Church teaching, it is not yet clear to what extent we may assess the burden of a patient’s total care rather than the burden of a particular treatment when we seek to refuse “burdensome” life support. On a practical level, those seeking to make good decisions might assure themselves of their own intentions by asking: Does my decision aim at relieving the patient of a particularly grave burden imposed by medically assisted nutrition and hydration? Or does it aim to avoid the total burden of caring for the patient? If so, does it achieve this aim by deliberately bringing about his or her death?

Rather than leaving families to confront such dilemmas alone, society and government should improve their assistance to families whose financial and emotional resources are strained by long-term care of loved ones.[28]

5. What role should “quality of life” play in our decisions?
Financial and emotional burdens are willingly endured by most families to raise their children or to care for mentally aware but weak and elderly family members. It is sometimes argued that we need not endure comparable burdens to feed and care for persons with severe mental and physical disabilities, because their low “quality of life” makes it unnecessary or pointless to preserve their lives.[29]

But this argument — even when it seems motivated by a humanitarian concern to reduce suffering and hardship — ignores the equal dignity and sanctity of all human life. Its key assumption — that people with disabilities necessarily enjoy life less than others or lack the potential to lead meaningful lives — is also mistaken.[30] Where suffering does exist, society’s response should not be to neglect or eliminate the lives of people with disabilities, but to help correct their inadequate living conditions.[31] Very often the worst threat to a good “quality of life” for these people is not the disability itself, but the prejudicial attitudes of others–attitudes based on the idea that a life with serious disabilities is not worth living.[32]

This being said, our moral tradition allows for three ways in which the “quality of life” of a seriously ill patient is relevant to treatment decisions:
1. Consistent with respect for the inherent sanctity of life, we should relieve needless suffering and support morally acceptable ways of improving each patient’s quality of life.[33]

2. One may legitimately refuse a treatment because it would itself create an impairment imposing new serious burdens or risks on the patient. This decision to avoid the new burdens or risks created by a treatment is not the same as directly intending to end life in order to avoid the burden of living in a disabled state.[34]

3. Sometimes a disabling condition may directly influence the benefits and burdens of a specific treatment for a particular patient. For example, a confused or demented patient may find medically assisted nutrition and hydration more frightening and burdensome than other patients do because he or she cannot understand what it is. The patient may even repeatedly pull out feeding tubes, requiring burdensome physical restraints if this form of feeding is to be continued. In such cases, ways of alleviating such special burdens should be explored before concluding that they justify withholding all food and fluids needed to sustain life.

These humane considerations are quite different from a “quality of life” ethic that would judge individuals with disabilities or limited potential as not worthy of care or respect. It is one thing to withhold a procedure because it would impose new disabilities on a patient, and quite another thing to say that patients who already have such disabilities should not have their lives preserved. A means considered ordinary or proportionate for other patients should not be considered extraordinary or disproportionate for severely impaired patients solely because of a judgment that their lives are not worth living.

In short, while considerations regarding a person’s quality of life have some validity in weighing the burdens and benefits of medical treatment, at the present time in our society judgments about the quality of life are sometimes used to promote euthanasia. The Church must emphasize the sanctity of life of each person as a fundamental principle in all moral decisionmaking.

6. Do persistently unconscious patients represent a special case?
Even Catholics who accept the same basic moral principles may strongly disagree on how to apply them to patients who appear to be persistently unconscious — that is, those who are in a permanent coma or a “persistent vegetative state” (PVS).[35] Some moral questions in this area have not been explicitly resolved by the Church’s teaching authority.

On some points there is wide agreement among Catholic theologians:
1. An unconscious patient must be treated as a living human person with inherent dignity and value. Direct killing of such a patient is as morally reprehensible as the direct killing of anyone else. Even the medical terminology used to describe these patients as “vegetative” unfortunately tends to obscure this vitally important point, inviting speculation that a patient in this state is a “vegetable” or a subhuman animal.[36]

2. The area of legitimate controversy does not concern patients with conditions like mental retardation, senility, dementia or even temporary unconsciousness. Where serious disagreement begins is with the patient who has been diagnosed as completely and permanently unconscious after careful testing over a period of weeks or months.
Some moral theologians argue that a particular form of care or treatment is morally obligatory only when its benefits outweigh its burdens to a patient or the care providers. In weighing burdens, they say, the total burden of a procedure and the consequent requirements of care must be taken into account. If no benefit can be demonstrated, the procedure, whatever its burdens, cannot be obligatory. These moralists also hold that the chief criterion to determine the benefit of a procedure cannot be merely that it prolongs physical life, since physical life is not an absolute good but is relative to the spiritual good of the person. They assert that the spiritual good of the person is union with God, which can be advanced only by human acts, i.e., conscious, free acts. Since the best current medical opinion holds that persons in the persistent vegetative state (PVS) are incapable now or in the future of conscious, free human acts, these moralists conclude that, when careful diagnosis verifies this condition, it is not obligatory to prolong life by such interventions as a respirator, antibiotics, or medically assisted hydration and nutrition. To decide to omit non-obligatory care, therefore, is not to intend the patient’s death, but only to avoid the burden of the procedure. Hence, though foreseen, the patient’s death is to be attributed to the patient’s pathological condition and not to the omission of care. Therefore, these theologians conclude, while it is always wrong directly to intend or cause the death of such patients, the natural dying process which would have occurred without these interventions may be permitted to proceed.

While this rationale is convincing to some, it is not theologically conclusive and we are not persuaded by it. In fact, other theologians argue cogently that theological inquiry could lead one to a more carefully limited conclusion.

These moral theologians argue that while particular treatments can be judged useless or burdensome, it is morally questionable and would create a dangerous precedent to imply that any human life is not a positive good or “benefit.” They emphasize that while life is not the highest good, it is always and everywhere a basic good of the human person and not merely a means to other goods. They further assert that if the “burden” one is trying to relieve by discontinuing medically assisted nutrition and hydration is the burden of remaining alive in the allegedly undignified condition of PVS, such a decision is unacceptable, because one’s intent is only achieved by deliberately ensuring the patient’s death from malnutrition or dehydration. Finally, these moralists suggest that PVS is best seen as an extreme form of mental and physical disability — one whose causes, nature and prognosis are as yet imperfectly understood — and not as a terminal illness or fatal pathology from which patients should generally be allowed to die. Because the patient’s life can often be sustained indefinitely by medically assisted nutrition and hydration that is not unreasonably risky or burdensome for that patient, they say, we are not dealing here with a case where “inevitable death is imminent in spite of the means used.”[37] Rather, because the patient will die in a few days if medically assisted nutrition and hydration are discontinued,[38] but can often live a long time if they are provided, the inherent dignity and worth of the human person obligates us to provide this patient with care and support.

Further complicating this debate is a disagreement over what responsible Catholics should do in the absence of a final resolution of this question. Some point to our moral tradition of probabilism, which would allow individuals to follow the appropriate moral analysis that they find persuasive. Others point to the principle that in cases where one might risk unjustly depriving someone of life, we should take the safer course.

In the face of the uncertainties and unresolved medical and theological issues, it is important to defend and preserve important values. On the one hand, there is a concern that patients and families should not be subjected to unnecessary burdens, ineffective treatments and indignities when death is approaching. On the other hand, it is important to ensure that the inherent dignity of human persons, even those who are persistently unconscious, is respected, and that no one is deprived of nutrition and hydration with the intent of bringing on his or her death.

It is not easy to arrive at a single answer to some of the real and personal dilemmas involved in this issue. In study, prayer and compassion we continue to reflect on this issue and hope to discover additional information that will lead to its ultimate resolution.

In the meantime, at a practical level, we are concerned that withdrawal of all life support, including nutrition and hydration, not be viewed as appropriate or automatically indicated for the entire class of PVS patients simply because of a judgment that they are beyond the reach of medical treatment that would restore consciousness. We note the current absence of conclusive scientific data on the causes and implications of different degrees of brain damage, on the PVS patient’s ability to experience pain, and on the reliability of prognoses for many such patients.[39] We do know that many of these patients have a good prognosis for long-term survival when given medically assisted nutrition and hydration, and a certain prognosis for death otherwise — and we know that many in our society view such an early death as a positive good for a patient in this condition. Therefore we are gravely concerned about current attitudes and policy trends in our society that would too easily dismiss patients without apparent mental faculties as non-persons or as undeserving of human care and concern. In this climate, even legitimate moral arguments intended to have a careful and limited application can easily be misinterpreted, broadened and abused by others to erode respect for the lives of some of our society’s most helpless members.

In light of these concerns, it is our considered judgment that while legitimate Catholic moral debate continues, decisions about these patients should be guided by a presumption in favor of medically assisted nutrition and hydration. A decision to discontinue such measures should be made in light of a careful assessment of the burdens and benefits of nutrition and hydration for the individual patient and his or her family and community. Such measures must not be withdrawn in order to cause death, but they may be withdrawn if they offer no reasonable hope of sustaining life or pose excessive risks or burdens. We also believe that social and health care policies should be carefully framed so that these patients are not routinely classified as “terminal” or as prime candidates for the discontinuance of even minimal means of life support.

7. Who should make decisions about medically assisted nutrition and hydration?
“Who decides?” In our society many believe this is the most important or even the only important question regarding this issue; and many understand it in terms of who has legal status to decide. Our Catholic tradition is more concerned with the principles for good moral decisionmaking, which apply to everyone involved in a decision. Some general observations are appropriate here.

A competent patient is the primary decisionmaker about his or her own health care, and is in the best situation to judge how the benefits and burdens of a particular procedure will be experienced. Ideally the patient will act with the advice of loved ones, of health care personnel who have expert knowledge of medical aspects of the case, and of pastoral counselors who can help explore the moral issues and spiritual values involved. A patient may wish to make known his or her general wishes about life support in advance; such expressions cannot have the weight of a fully informed decision made in the actual circumstances of an illness, but can help guide others in the event of a later state of incompetency.[40] Morally even the patient making decisions for himself or herself is bound by norms that prohibit the directly intended causing of death through action or omission, and by the distinction between ordinary and extraordinary means.

When a patient is not competent to make his or her own decisions, a proxy decisionmaker who shares the patient’s moral convictions, such as a family member or guardian, may be designated to represent the patient’s interests and interpret his or her wishes. Here, too, moral limits remain relevant — that is, morally the proxy may not deliberately cause a patient’s death or refuse what is clearly ordinary means, even if he or she believes the patient would have made such a decision.

Health care personnel should generally follow the reasonable wishes of patient or family, but must also consult their own consciences when participating in these decisions. A physician or nurse told to participate in a course of action that he or she views as clearly immoral has a right and responsibility either to refuse to participate in this course of action or to withdraw from the case, and he or she should be given the opportunity to express the reasons for such refusal in the appropriate forum. Social and legal policies must protect such rights of conscience.

Finally, because these are matters of life and death for human persons, society as a whole has a legitimate interest in responsible decisionmaking.[41]

For futher information on Medically Assisted Nutrition and Hydration, please see http://www.usccb.org/prolife/

Please also visit www.terrisfight.org, the website begun by the Schindler family, soon after Terri Schindler Schiavo was killed through starvation in 2005, as a result of her nutrition and hydration being stopped.


Moral Principles Conclusion

Endnotes
11. Archbishop John Roach, “Life-support removal: No easy answers,” Catholic Bulletin, March 7, 1991, page 1 (citing Bio/medical Ethics Commission of the Archdiocese of St. Paul-Minneapolis).
12. “If all fluids and nutirition are withdrawn from any patient, regardless of the condition, he or she will die–inevitably and invariably. Death may come in a few days or take up to two weeks. Rarely in medicine is an earlier death for the patient so certain.” Ronald E. Cranford, M.D., “Patients with Permanent Loss of Consciousness,” in Joanne Lynn (ed.), By No Extraordinary Means (Indiana University Press 1986), page 191.
13. See the arguments made by a judge in the Elizabeth Bouvia case, and byt attorneys in the Hector Rodas case, among others. See Bouvia v. Superior Court, 225 Cal. Rptr. 297, 307-8 (1986) (Compton, J., concurring); Complaint for Declaratory Relief in Rodas Case, Issues in Law & Medicine, Volume 2 (1987)m pages 499-501, quoted verbatim from Rodas v. Erkenbrack, No. 87 ev 142 (Mesa County, Colo., filed Jan. 30, 1987).
14. As one medical ethicist observes, interest in a broadly permissive policy for removing nutrition and hydration has grown “because a denial of nutrition may in the long run become the only effective way to make certain that a large number of biologically tenacious patients actually die.” Daniel Callahan, “On Feeding the Dying,” Hastings Center Report, Volume 13 (October 1983), page 22.
15. See Moral Principles above, no. 5.
16. Address to a Human Pre-Leukaemia Conference, November 15, 1985: AAS, Volume 78 (1986), page 361. Also see his October 21, 1985 address to a study group of the Pontifical Academy of Sciences: “Even when the sick are incurable they are never untreatable; whatever their condition, appropriate care should be provided for them.” AAS, Volume 78 (1986), page 314; Origins, Volume 15 (December 5, 1985), page 416.
17. Some groups advising the Holy See have ventured opinions on this point, but these do not have the force of official Church teaching. For example, in 1985 a study group of the Pontifical Academy of Sciences concluded: “If the patient is in a permanent, irreversible coma, as far as can be foreseen, treatment is not required, but all care should be lavished on him, including feeding.” Pontifical Academy of Sciences, “The Artificial Prolongation of Life,” Origins, Volume 15 (December 5, 1985), page 415. Since comatose patients cannot generally take food orally, the statement evidently refers to medically assisted feeding. Similar statements are found in: Pontifical Council Cor Unum, Question of Ethics Regarding the Fatally Ill and the Dying (1981), page 9; “Ne Euthanasia Ne Accanimento Terapeutico,” La Civilta Cattolica, Volume 3280 (February 21, 1987), page 324.
18. World Medical Association, Declaration of Helsinki (1975), II.1.
19. See Joyce V. Zerwekh, “The Dehydration Question,” Nursing83 (January 1983), pages 47-51.
20. See William E. May et al., “Feeding and Hydrating the Permanently Unconscious and Other Vulnerable Persons,” Issues in Law and Medicine, Volume 2 (Winter 1987), page 208.
21. Ronald E. Cranford, “The Persistent Vegetative State: The Medical Reality (Getting the Facts Straight), “Hastings Center Report, Volume 18 (February/March 1988), page 31.
22. Declaration on Euthanasia, Part IV (emphasis added).
23. Current ethical guideline for nurses, while generally defending patient autonomy, reflect this concern: “Obligations to prevent harm and bring benefit . . . require that nurses seek to understand the patient’s reasons for refusal . . . Nurses should make every effort to correct inaccurate views, to modify superficially held beliefs and overly dramatic gestures, and to resotre hope where there is reason to hope.” American Nurses’ Association Committtee on Ethics, “Guideline on Withdrawing or Withholding Food and Fluid,” Biolaw, Volume 2 (October 1988), pages U1124-5.
24. In one such study, “seventy percent of patients and families were 100% willing to undergo intensive care again to achieve even one month of survival”; “age, severity of critical illness, length of stay, and charges for intensive care did not influence willingness to undergo intensive care.” Danis et al., “Patients’ and Families’ Preferences for Medical Intensive Care,” Journal of the American Medical Association, Volume 260 (August 12, 1988), page 797. In another study, out of 33 people who had clse relatives in a “persistent vegetative state,” 29 agreed with the intial decision to initiate tube feeding and 25 strongly agreed that such feeding should be continued, although none of those surveyed had made the decision to initiate it. Tresch et al., “Patients in a Persistent Vegatative State: Attitudes and Reactions of Family Members,” Journal of the American Geriatrics Society, Vol. 39 (January 1991), pages 17-21.
25. Declaration on Euthanasia, Part IV.
26. “In striving to contain medical care costs, it is important to avoid discriminating against the critically ill and dying, to shun individious comparisons of the economic value of various individuals to society, and to refuse to abandon patients and hasten death to save money.” Hastings Center, Guidelines on the Termination of Life Sustaining Treatment and the Care of the Dying (Hastings Center 1987), page 120.
27. A possible exception is total parenteral feeding, which requires carefully prepared sterile formulas and more intensive daily monitoring. Ironically, some current health care policies may exert economic pressure in favor of TPN beacuse it is easier to obtain third-party reimbursement. Families may pay more for other forms of feeding because some insurance companies do not see them as “medical treatment.” See U.S. Congress, Office of Technology Assessment, Life-Sustaining Technologies and the Elderly, OTA-BA-306 (Washington, D.C.: July 1987), page 286.
28. “One can never claim that one wishes to bring comfort to a family by supressing one of its members. The respect, the dedication, the time and means required for the care of handicapped persons, even of those whose mental faculties are gravely affected, is the price that a society would generously pay in order to remain truly human.” Document of the Holy See, note 9 supra, II.1: Origins at 748. The Holy See acknowledges that society as a whole should willingly assume these burdens, not leave them on the shoulders on individuals and families.
29. E.g., see P. Singer, “Sanctity of Life or Quality of Life?”, Pediatrics, Volume 72 (July 1983), pp. 128-9. On the use and misuse of the term “quality of life” see John Cardinal O’Connor, “Who Will Care for the AIDS Victims?”, Origins, Volume 19 (Juanuary 18, 1990), pages 544-8.Some Catholic theologians argue that a low “quality of life” justifies withdrawal of medically assisted feeding only from patients diagnosed as permanently unconscious. This argument is discussed separately in section 6 below.
30. See David Milne, “Urges Mds to Get Birth Defects Patient’s Own Story,” Medical Tribune (December 12, 1979), page 6.
31. U.S. Catholic Conference, Pastoral Statement of the United States Catholic Bishops on Handicapped People (November 15, 1978). Published in Nolan (ed.), Pastoral Letters of the United States Catholic Bishops (USCC 1984), Volume IV, page 269.
32. Some patients with disabilities ask for death because all their efforts to build a life of self-r

espect are thwarted; a “right to die” is the first right for which they recieve enthusiastic supprt from the able-bodied. See Paul K. Longmore, “Elizabeth Bouvia, Assisted Suicide and Social Prejudice,” Issues in Law & Medicine, Volume 3 (Fall 1987), pages 141-168.
33. “Quality of life must be sought, in so far as it is possible, by proportionate and appropriate threatment, but it presupposes life and the right to life for everyone, without discrimination and abandonment.” Pope John Paul II, Address of April 14, 1988 to the eleventh European Congress of Perinatal Medicine: AAS, Volume 80 (1988), page 1426; The Pope Speaks, Volume 33 (1988), pages 264-5.
34. See Archbishop Roger Mahony, “Two Statements on the Bouvia Case,” Linacre Quarterly, Vol. 55 (February 1988), pages 85-7.
35. Coma and persistent vegetative state are not the same. Coma, strictly speaking, is generally not a long term condition, for within a few weeks a comatose patient usually dies, recovers, or reaches the plateau of a persistent vegetative state. “Coma implies the absence of both arousal and content. In terms of observable behavior, the comatose patient appears to be asleep, but unlike the sleeping patient, he cannot be aroused from this state . . . the patient in the vegetative state appears awake but shows no evidence of content, either confused or appropriate. He often has sleep-wake cycles but cannot demonstrate an awareness of himself or his environment.” Levy, “The Comatose Patient,” in Rosenberg (ed.), The Clinical Neurosciences (Churchill Livingstone 1983), Volume I, page 956.
36. While the perjorative connotation was surely not intended by those coining the phrase, we invite the medical profession to consider a less discriminatory term for this diagnostic state.
37. See Moral Principles above, no. 5.
38. Because patients need nutritional support to live during the weeks and months of observation required for a responsible assessment of PVS, the cases discussed here involve decisions about discounting such support rather than intiating it.
39. One recent scientific study of recovery rates followed up 84 patients with a firm diagnosis of PVS. Of these patients, “41% became conscious by 6 months, 52% regained their consciousness by 1 year, and 58% recovered consciousness within the 3-year follow-up inteval.” The study was unable to identify “predictors of recovery from the vegetative state” — that is, there is no established test by which physicians can tell in advance which PVS patients will ultimately wake up. The data “do not exclude the possiblility of vegetative patients regaining consciousness after the second year,” though this “must be ragarded as a rare event.” Levin, Saydjari et al., “Vegetative State After Closed-Head Injury: A Traumatic Coma Data Bank Report,” Archives of Neurology, Volume 48 (June 1991), pages 580-585.
40. Some Catholic moralists, using the concept of a “virtual intention,” note that a person may give spiritual significance to his or her later suffering during incompetency, by deciding in advance to join these sufferings with those of Christ for the redemption of others.
41. See: NCCB Committee for Pro-Life Activities, Guidelines for Legislation on Life-Sustaining Treatment (November 10, 1984), published in Origins, Volume 14 (January 24, 1985); Id., Statement on the Uniform Rights of the Terminally Ill Act (June 1986), published in Origins, Volume 16 (September 4, 1986); U.S. Petitioners, Cruzan v. Director of Missouri Department on Health v. McCanse, U.S. Supreme Court, No.88-1503, published in Origins, Volume 19 (October 26, 1989), pages 345-351.



Secretariat for Pro-Life Activities
United States Conference of Catholic Bishops
3211 4th Street, N.E., Washington, DC 20017-1194 (202) 541-3070
June 03, 2003 Copyright © by United States Conference of Catholic Bishops

Return to the Respect Life Page

Rectory & Hours

622 Putnam Pike
Greenville, RI 02828
P: (401) 949-1500
E:office@saintphilip.com

Monday-Friday: 8:30am to 4:30pm

Contact Us

Out of town?  Looking for a Catholic Mass?

Catholic Church Mass Times